The usable Gramsci?
Martin Thomas
Platypus Review 144 | March 2022
THE SIX RECENT CONTRIBUTIONS I will survey here mostly seek to identify an Antonio Gramsci usable for active socialist politics amidst the welter of Gramscis around us. They construct their usable Gramscis mostly from the terms which have figured largest in the âorthodoxâ Gramscis since the 1950s (the Italian Communist Partyâs (PCI), the Eurocommunist, and then the academic): hegemony and war of position. My case will be that active socialists can gain more from seeing Gramsciâs arguments around those terms as weak areas, and starting with stronger seams of Gramsciâs writing.
Jan Norden finds nothing usable.[1] He interprets Gramsciâs argument about hegemony as that âbefore considering the seizure of political power, one would first have to struggle to conquer cultural leadership.â The decisive word in this presentation is âculturalâ: that socialists have to struggle to win political leadership in the working class before seizure of political power is only a commonplace rejection of putschism. With the tweak to âcultural,â however, Norden identifies the âGramscianâ argument as one suited to âformer leftist students turned academics.â
Gramsci himself did not drift from activism to academia, but Norden indicts him in 1919â20 as complicit in the Italian Socialist Party (SP) leadersâ âeternal waiting.â (Gramsci was at the time a young activist with a small group of co-thinkers in Turin. He was unable to solidify an Italy-wide faction to challenge the SP leaders effectively, as also was Amadeo Bordiga, the more established leader of the revolutionary wing of the SP.) Norden also indicts the Trotskyist Faction and Left Voice as being ready to âraise a transitional program which includes the defense of bourgeois democracy,â and sees Gramscianism there. Trotsky, claims Norden, ânever presented a âprogram of radical democracy.ââ[2] Yet Section 16 of the âProgram of Action for Franceâ written by Trotsky in June 1934 was exactly that.
Massimo Amadori equally identifies his Gramsci as one of âwar of positionâ and âcultural hegemony,â but approvingly.[3] âWar of positionâ is just a âperspective [which] did not exclude united fronts with other left forces and struggles for democratic goals;â the âconcept of âcultural hegemonyââ was âan attempt by Gramsci to adapt a Leninist strategy to a Western contextâ and was âalso present in the work of Lenin.â[4] This account, in its own way, yields as little âusable Gramsciâ as Nordenâs: the usable ideas are already available, and less cryptically-worded, in Lenin.
Lenin advocated âhegemonyâ of the working class in the fight against autocracy in Russia. In a 1911 polemic against liquidationists, he wrote, âThe hegemony of the working class is the political influence which that class (and its representatives) exercises upon other sections of the population by helping them to purge their democracy (where there is democracy) of undemocratic admixtures, by criticising the narrowness and short-sightedness of all bourgeois democracy, by carrying on the struggle against âCadetismâ [...], etc.â[5] The Russian Marxists did not write about âcultural hegemony.â Neither, mostly, did Gramsci. Before prison Gramsci had criticized the early issues of LâOrdine Nuovo[6] as an âanthologyâ of âabstract culture,â before it was reoriented to the Turin factory councils.[7] In Russia in 1922â23 he had contributed a chapter to Trotskyâs Literature and Revolution (1924). He must have been aware of the polemics by Trotsky against the idea that a âproletarian cultureâ could become hegemonic even after a socialist revolution. The working class would have much to do to educate itself even in bourgeois culture. By the time that was complete and class divisions had withered, the new culture would be âsocialistâ rather than âproletarian.â Gramsci never disputed that view, which won out among the Bolsheviks.
The word âhegemonyâ appears often in the Prison Notebooks, and the words âcultureâ and âculturalâ too. The term âcultural hegemonyâ appears rarely, and, as far as I can make out, as part of formulations like âpolitical and cultural hegemony,â or âcultural and moral hegemony.â The Notebooks equate âculturalâ with âethico-political,â or with the combination-merger of politics and philosophy, or just with âethical,â rather than with âthe artsâ and such. Gramsci argues not for replacing political activity by diffuse cultural promotion, but for a âbroadâ conception of politics, embracing reflection on different ethics and ways of life, rather than a narrow one. Even before prison, Gramsci had described LâOrdine Nuovo (after its reorientation) as a âcommunist cultural review,â though in fact it was a political newspaper, with a broad range of coverage. âThe nature of the philosophy of praxis is [...] that of being a mass conception, a mass culture [...] The activity of the âindividualâ philosopher cannot therefore be conceived except in terms of this social unity, i.e. also as political activity, in terms of political leadership.â[8]
Michael Denning also equates Gramsci with âwar of positionâ and a cultural focus, only he argues that the usable version of these ideas today is to inform the activity of âorganizersâ in the Saul Alinsky tradition.[9] Previously, he writes, there have been âtwo major forms of Gramscian politics.â[10] One was through political party activity, and he identifies the Italian Communist Party of the 1950sâ80s as an authentic exemplar. The second form was a âwar of position across the cultural organizations [...] in education, journalism, popular culture, and philosophy.â[11] Both forms, he says, "seem exhausted.â
Today, Denning claims, âyoung activists think of themselves as organizers (of a variety of stripes) not as partisans (party members).â[12] They can work at âthe reformation of the national-popular collective willâin the workplace, the neighbourhood, the household, the police precinct, even the legislature.â[13] Alexandria Ocasio-Cortez, he reminds us, has said, ââThe way that I think of myself is an organizer [...] building a coalition, deepening that coalition with other organizers.ââ[14] The usable Gramsci can take us beyond âthe received US ideology of organizing, which tends to bracket âideologicalâ issues from âpragmaticâ concerns.â[15]
Denning takes his cue from Gramsciâs comment that âeveryone is a legislator in the broadest sense of the word.â[16] That comment parallels Gramsciâs more famous remark that âeveryone is a philosopher;â[17] everyone has a âconception of the worldâ (philosophy) embedded in our communications, even if lacking in self-awareness, critical working-through, and coherence. Everyone is a âlegislatorâ in the sense of promoting âânormsâ, rules of living and of behaviourâ in our own circle.[18] But the ruling class are, by definition, the decisive âlegislators;â the working class can become âlegislatorsâ in more than a minimal or notional sense only by taking power, and that can be done only after we (or enough of us) have become âphilosophersâ in a more critically-worked-through way.
The shift from âeveryone a philosopherâ to âeveryone a legislatorâ signals a shift from developing a unified and coherent political force to establishing oppositional âânormsâ, rules of livingâ in a scattershot variety of areas. That is to be done by the âorganisers,â which in the U.S. means the vast numbers of Left-minded young people employed by ânonprofits,â community organizations, labor unions, NGOs, etc. Even if the âorganizersâ question Saul Alinskyâs original emphasis on pragmatism against ideology, as Jane McAlevey for example does, and emphasize in-person conversation on the ground above electronic messaging from an office, as McAlevey also does, this gives us a tame and diffuse âusable Gramsci.â
Nicholas Stender offers a âusable Gramsciâ which contrasts with both the image of socialist âhegemonyâ welling up from below through miscellaneous organizing efforts, and that of it seeping down from incremental efforts in cultural institutions.[19] He cites as Gramsciâs image of bourgeois hegemony an outburst of October 1919: âThe revolution finds the broad masses of the Italian people still shapeless, still atomised into an animal-like swarm of individuals lacking all discipline and culture, obedient only to the stimuli of their bellies and their barbarian passions.â[20] Winning socialist hegemony is about the socialists educating that âswarm.â Stender does not mention âwar of position;â his âusable Gramsciâ focuses on another well-known term, the âorganic intellectual.â âOrganic intellectuals,â he explains, are class-conscious workers who educate their workmates: they are enabled to do so by the discipline of a revolutionary party.[21]
In his writings before jail, Gramsci occasionally vented exasperation against people around him, most of all urban petty officials and professionals drawn from the rural population, but also sometimes workers or even the dilatory members of his own party, as âlacking discipline and culture.â A major element, however, and a valuable one, of the discussion of âhegemonyâ he later developed in the Prison Notebooks, was the thought that what socialists characteristically have to deal with in the working class and the middle classes is different forms of âdiscipline and culture,â not a shapeless absolute lack of it: namely, a âdiscipline and cultureâ shaped both by the many ideological workings of the bourgeois state and other bourgeois institutions and by class activities. To replace those contradictory forms of âdiscipline and cultureâ by a coherent socialist form requires both discerning and building on the solidaristic and emancipatory elements in peopleâs previous multifaceted thinking, and educating ourselves sufficiently to tackle the bourgeois ideologies even in their best forms.
I find Gramsciâs dichotomy between âtraditionalâ and âorganicâ intellectuals one of his most confused conceptualisations. He writes that âEvery social group, coming into existence on the original terrain of an essential function in the world of economic production, creates together with itself, organically, one or more strata of intellectualsâ (technicians, economists, lawyers, entrepreneurs, etc. for the capitalist class); it also finds âcategories of intellectuals already in existence and which seemed indeed to represent an historical continuity uninterrupted even by the most complicated and radical changes in political and social forms.â[22] The archetype for Gramsci of the second-type âtraditionalâ intellectuals is âecclesiastics.â In the Italy of Gramsciâs day the Catholic Church was a great ideological power but maintained distance from bourgeois governments: from 1868 to 1918 it enjoined the faithful neither to vote nor to stand in elections. No wonder Gramsci wanted to explore the role of the priests as a special body of intellectuals. Dissolving that specific problem into a universal dichotomy between âorganicâ and âtraditionalâ intellectuals does not help. Other sorts of intellectuals whom he described as âtraditionalâ were âthe man of letters, the philosopher, the poet.â[23] But, in fact, to be a qualified technician or lawyer requires training in a âtraditionâ of knowledge going back over centuries and relatively independent of the ruling class of the day, whereas you can be a poet without rooting your work in knowledge of previous poetry. Gramsci elsewhere emphasizes the need for the working-class socialist movement to win over technicians, supposedly the archetypal âorganic intellectualsâ of the capitalist class. Trade-union officials, in a stable liberal bourgeois democracy, are simultaneously âorganic intellectualsâ both of the working class (by day-to-day efforts to represent worker interests) and of the capitalist class (by disseminating ideas of class conciliation). In latter-day efforts to construct a âusable Gramsci,â the term âorganic intellectualâ tends to become a term for someone deemed âin touch.â (For example, an obituary of the prominent âpost-Gramscian,â Ernesto Laclau, refers to him, son of a diplomat and a lawyer, and an academic all his adult life, as an âorganic intellectual.â[24]) Stenderâs use of the term can serve no more than to give members of his group the glow of feeling that, if they are disciplined and promote the groupâs politics assiduously, then they become âorganic intellectuals,â who as such, even if they know little, become superior to âtraditional intellectuals.â
Chris Maisano explicitly rejects a âculturalistâ reading of hegemony.[25] He argues that hegemony in Gramsci is centrally about politics: âIs hegemony, a fundamentally cultural concept for Gramsci, as it is for many of his supposed followers? [...] It is not.â[26] âWhat Gramsci called the ethico-political dimension of political struggle has little to do with the emphasis on storytelling and communication strategy thatâs so common in the NGO sector today. It refers instead to the creation of an integral worldview grounded in the workersâ experiences of daily life through a protracted process of collective political education and organization-building.â[27]
Maisanoâs âusable Gramsci,â however, promotes âwar of positionâ as describing a strategy required in more advanced capitalist states, in contrast to âwar of maneuverâ supposedly exemplified by the October 1917 Revolution in Russia. He indicates that he finds the approach of the Italian Communist Party from the 1950s to the 1980s a genuine, though not flawless, exemplar:
Thereâs a lot that you can still get out of Gramsci and his writings and, I think, also the historical practice [...] of the Italian Communist Party. [...] Gramsci and [...] many of [...] his milieu [...] were concerned above all else with remaining in contact with the masses of working people in their society. The tension here is that, and I think the Italian Communists faced this [is that] if you do succeed, I think in building up a large organization or set of organizations within the shell of the broader capitalist society, that is going to make people [...] interested in [...] maintaining them, keeping them going [...] on their own terms and not doing anything that might threaten or disrupt their ongoing existence, that would threaten their institutional or political survival [...] Itâs a real dilemma [...] The Left nowhere has really figured out how to do that. The Italian Communists did not [...] Here in the United States, weâve never had the opportunity, unfortunately, to actually grapple with that dilemma.[28]
But, he indicates, for now letâs get to the point where the dilemma arises.
There is âGramscianâ sense, in my view, against political approaches on the revolutionary Left, which focus almost entirely on boosting immediate economic and similar militancy, with the implied perspective that enough of that plus economic crisis will eventually explode into revolution as long as a big enough revolutionary organization has been built â âalmost entirelyâ to the extent that battles for democracy, patient education, sober appraisal and so on are downplayed. A passage from the Prison Notebooks which reads like a critique of strands of Bordigaâs thought is relevant. Gramsci criticizes:
The iron conviction that there exist objective laws of historical development similar in kind to natural laws [...] favourable conditions are inevitably going to appear, and [...] these, in a rather mysterious way, will bring about palingenetic events [...] Side by side with these fatalistic beliefs, however, there exists the tendency âthereafterâ to rely blindly and indiscriminately on the regulatory properties of armed conflict. [...] Destruction is conceived of mechanically, not as destruction/reconstruction. In such modes of thinking, no account is taken of the âtimeâ factor, nor in the last analysis even of âeconomics.â For there is no understanding of the fact that mass ideological factors always lag behind mass economic phenomena, and that therefore, at certain moments, the automatic thrust due to the economic factor is slowed down, obstructed or even momentarily broken by traditional ideological elements â hence that there must be a conscious, planned struggle to ensure that the exigencies of the economic position of the masses, which may conflict with the traditional leadershipâs policies, are understood. An appropriate political initiative is always necessary to liberate the economic thrust from the dead weight of traditional policies [...].[29]
However, Maisanoâs âusable Gramsciâ goes beyond that to become an authority for the âanti-insurrectionary,â âtransformative reforms,â ârevolutionary social democracyâ wing of the Democratic Socialists of America and, more, for assimilating that wing to the approach of the Italian Communist Party between the 1950s and the 1980s and taking it as an exemplar of âusable Gramsci.â
Francesco Giliani offers a crisp demolition of the example.[30] The PCIâs approach was already flatly reformist and class-collaborationist when it emerged from clandestinity with the fall of Mussolini in 1943â45. It did not just fail at the final hurdle on counteracting the inevitable conservatism which arises after relative positions of strength are won. From the 1940s onwards the PCI constructed âa Gramsci who rigidly opposed the war of position (i.e. the slow construction of an anti-capitalist bloc) to the war of manoeuvre (i.e. an open offensive against the bourgeoisie).â[31] (In fact, the âblocâ constructed was not really even anti-capitalist: its aim was the PCIâs inclusion in a governing coalition, or a more âadvanced democracy.â with actual anti-capitalism relegated to a distant next stage.)
Maisano seeks to dissociate his âusable Gramsciâ from the Gramsci misused by advocates of the pursuit of loose cultural influence as a substitute for political activity. Why, he asks, was Gramsci vulnerable to such misuse? âGramsciâs work doesnât really get translated into English until the 70s [...] And this is precisely the period in which the Left, the working-class movement, labor movements are starting to come under very serious attack in many capitalist countries [and] largely defeated [...] The most iconic example of that being Margaret Thatcherâs defeat of the coal minersâ strike in Britain in 1984 and 1985 [...] [Gramsciâs] discussions of popular culture or ideology [...] created, I think, an opening for people who may have been, say, dispirited or disappointed by the various defeats [...] [and for] quite one-sided readings of a lot of his work.â[32]
Maisanoâs chronology is wrong. As Giliani shows, a Gramsci âusableâ for reformism had been formulated by the PCI leaders decades before. It was disseminated internationally long before the defeats of the 1980s; and contested by revolutionaries, too.[33] Sizeable one-volume selections from Gramsci were published in French in 1959, in German in 1957, and in Spanish in 1970. The ferment in the French Communist Party student organization in the early 1960s which would in 1966 produce sizable Trotskyist and Maoist spin-offs, also featured a âpro-Italianâ faction, though that subsided. A short Gramsci selection was published in English in 1957. New Left Review published a PCI-like âGramscianâ account of âProblems of Socialist Strategyâ in 1965. The large Selections from the Prison Notebooks were published in 1971, and debated over a full decade of Left-wing buoyancy before Thatcher started dispersing and dismaying it.
In the 1970s, the PCIâs approach gained ground with other Communist Party leaderships and educated thousands of activists in so-called âEurocommunism.â The further step from âEurocommunismâ to a âGramsciâ one-sidedly âculturalistâ and with scant or no relation to the working class or socialism came with the decline, dissipation, and sometimes winding-up of the Communist Parties in the 1980s and early 1990s, a process driven by the decay and then sudden collapse of the command economies in Eastern Europe and the USSR. Thousands of people concluded that what they had thought to be socialism was unviable and maybe not even desirable. Those who wished to continue to be active in a Leftish way could adapt the âusable Gramsciâ of the 1950sâ60s PCI and later Eurocommunism just by deleting some tenuous âin the last analysisâ connections.
Gilianiâs article, a solid and useful piece of work, also gives a reasoned dissection of the fumblings of Gramsciâs policy when he was leader of the PCI between 1923 and 1926. Giliani does not dismiss Gramsci in the way that Norden does, but the focus of his article is not on a âusable Gramsciâ for revolutionary socialists, rather on dissecting the PCIâs and Eurocommunistsâ âusable Gramsci.â Giliani refers to Perry Andersonâs book (originally published in 1976 as a special issue of New Left Review) on The Antinomies of Antonio Gramsci. That Gramsci should be âusableâ by the PCI and such requires no special explanation. Marx, Lenin, and others have in their time been made âusableâ by people using shreds of quotation to aliment politics quite different from the authorsâ. Since Gramsciâs Prison Notebooks are a miscellany of short notes, written in difficult conditions, often cryptic, the adaptation to varied purposes is even easier. Anderson argues that there are internal âantinomiesâ in Gramsciâs writings which facilitate it. Gramsci usually locates hegemony as operating in âcivil societyâ and by means of developing âconsent.â But many constructions of bourgeois consent operate through the state (for example, the very structures of bourgeois democracy, as distinct from the parties which can be located in âcivil societyâ) or by âdull economic compulsionâ (commodity fetishism); and there is âcoercionâ in civil society. Gramsci often omits economic structures from civil society. The theoretical construction makes almost invisible the difference between bourgeois democracy and fascism. The âwar of positionâ argument sometimes approximates Karl Kautskyâs âattrition strategyâ developed in polemic against Rosa Luxemburg in 1910â11.
Indeed, more can be said along Andersonâs lines.[34] We should take Gramsciâs own warning: âComparisons between military art and politics, if made, should always be taken [...] with a pinch of salt [...] In political struggle, there also exist other forms of warfareâapart from the war of movement [...] or the war of position.â[35] Even within those limits, suggestions that we must have âwar of positionâ today in contrast to Bolshevik âwar of maneuverâ rest on a misperception of the October 1917 Revolution as having been made by a sudden âfrontal offensiveâ once a quasi-military party organization had gained strength. In fact, the final uprising was much less spectacular than the February Revolution, and was prepared through a sinuous and careful selection of tactics and initiatives, mostly about winning âconsentâ (a majority in the soviets, and soviet authority in the population). The counterposition of East and West is schematic: Tsarist Russia had a ramshackle state machine, which moreover largely disintegrated after the February 1917 Revolution, while countries like Germany, Italy, or France had much more resilient state machines. Tsarist Russia had a complex civil society.
The Prison Notebooks were not written to investigate revolutionary socialist strategy in stable, or relatively stable, bourgeois democracies. Gramsci saw fascism as more typical for Europe in his day: âin the present epoch, the war of movement took place politically from March 1917 to March 1921: this was followed by a war of position whose representative â both practical (for Italy) and ideological (for Europe) is fascism.â[36] In what Gramsci saw as a more stable bourgeois democracy, the U.S., he misperceived, writing that there âhegemony is born in the factory and requires for its exercise only a minute quantity of professional and ideological intermediariesâ and that in the U.S. âthere [had] not been [...] any flowering of the âsuperstructure.ââ[37] Gramsci read Henry Fordâs tactics in his factories one-sidedly and over-generalized. In fact the U.S. has long had exceptionally many âprofessional and ideological intermediariesâ of bourgeois hegemony: lawyers, real-estate agents, professors, priests and pastors, university professors, politicians, etc.
When Gramsci discusses hegemony in the Prison Notebooks, he may have in mind fascist Italy, the Bolsheviksâ efforts to reassemble popular support in the New Economic Policy period, or liberal Italy from the Risorgimento to the World War â and sometimes it is difficult to know which â but never a latter-day relatively stable, urbanized, secular bourgeois democracy. Ideas from the Notebooksâ discussions of hegemony can be made âusableâ today, but only with selection and care. Gramsci was aware of the asymmetry between bourgeois ways of constructing hegemony (i.e. winning political leadership) and working-class socialist ways of doing that. âIn political struggle one should not ape the methods of the ruling classes.â[38] âThe philosophy of praxis [...] does not aim at the peaceful resolution of existing contradictions in history and society but is rather the very theory of these contradictions. It is not the instrument of government of the dominant groups in order to gain the consent of and exercise hegemony over the subaltern classes; it is the expression of these subaltern classes who want to educate themselves in the art of government and who have an interest in knowing all truths, even the unpleasant ones, and in avoiding the [...] deceptions of the upper class and â even more â their own.â[39] But on a first reading the Prison Notebooks often look like they are discussing techniques of hegemony equally usable by either class.
Gramsci did not write the Prison Notebooks as a guide to current politics. He was likely to be in jail for a long time; he was too ill to do much in current politics even if released from jail; he had little way of offering political direction to people outside; by the time the prison authorities permitted him to use pen and notebooks in 1929 he was out of tune with the now-Third-Period Communist Party yet felt unable to link with oppositional communists. So he chose to write on longer-range historical, philosophical, and scientific issues.
His writings diverged from his planning lists, but in those lists âthe development of Italian intellectualsâ was top in 1927, âformation of Italian intellectual groupsâ third in February 1929, âItalian history [...] with special attention to [...] intellectual groupsâ first in March 1929, âintellectualsâ first in MarchâApril 1932.[40] Some of the writing on âintellectualsâ was of a more distanced historical character. In some, though, he is discussing why the intellectual leaders of the Socialist Party were ineffectual in 1919â20; why the early Communist Party under Bordigaâs leadership was also ineffectual in a different way (membership went down from 40,000 in early 1921 to 5,000 in late 1923, and was rebuilt under Gramsciâs leadership, despite fascist rule, to over 25,000 before the full fascist clampdown in 1926); why Third-Period policies were folly; why the liberal intellectuals who had ruled Italy for decades collapsed so ignominiously before fascism; and why so many syndicalist intellectuals went over to fascism.
Those writings give us much âusable Gramsci.â For our time it helps that he was discussing political issues of long hauls, not responses to immediate crises, which dominated the writings of, for example, Trotsky in the 1930s. Gramsci went beyond generalities about hegemony or lack of it. The liberals had hegemony over the people of Italy for decades; the Socialist Party had hegemony in the Italian working class around the end of World War I. The question was why those âhegemoniesâ proved so ineffectual, which required an examination of what Gramsci called the âhegemonic apparatus.â
Gramsci moved away from the scheme, which spills into his pre-prison writings from time to time, of an enlightened few instructing an ignorant and thoughtless mass, and, in many âusableâ sections of his investigations, towards specifics of how and what sort of hegemony. He continued to insist that âinstructionâ is a vital element in education. It is not all âlearning by doing.â But he insisted on a positive engagement with âspontaneousâ class battles. ââPureâ spontaneity does not exist in history [...] In the âmost spontaneousâ movement it is simply the case that the elements of âconscious leadershipâ cannot be checked, have left no reliable document. It may be said that spontaneity is therefore characteristic of the âhistory of the subaltern classes.ââ[41] In the Turin movement of 1919â20, he wrote proudly:
This element of âspontaneityâ was not neglected and even less despised. It was educated, directed, purged of extraneous contaminations; the aim was to bring it into line with modern theory â but in a living and historically effective manner [...] Neglecting, or worse still despising, so-called âspontaneousâ movements, i.e. failing to give them a conscious leadership or to raise them to a higher plane by inserting them into politics, may often have extremely serious consequences. It is almost always the case that a âspontaneousâ movement of the subaltern classes is accompanied by a reactionary movement of the right-wing of the dominant class [...].[42]
Gramsciâs image for the socialist party âintellectualâ was the âpermanently active persuader,â or under conditions of bourgeois-democratic freedom, âthe democratic philosopherâ:
The environment reacts back on the philosopher and imposes on him a continual process of self-criticism [...] his personality [...] is an active social relationship of modification of the cultural environment.â[43] Socialist development of intellectuals and hegemony contrasts sharply with that of the Catholic Church. In the Catholic Church, the âsplit [between little-educated believers and the intellectuals] cannot be healed by raising the simple to the level of the intellectuals (the Church does not even envisage such a task, which is both ideologically and economically beyond its present capacities), but only by imposing an iron discipline on the intellectuals so that they do not exceed certain limits of differentiation and so render the split catastrophic and irreparable [...] The position of the philosophy of praxis is the antithesis of the Catholic. The philosophy of praxis does not tend to leave the âsimpleâ in their primitive philosophy of common sense, but rather to lead them to a higher conception of life. If it affirms the need for contact between intellectuals and simple it is not in order to restrict scientific activity and preserve unity at the low level of the masses, but precisely in order to construct an intellectual-moral bloc which can make politically possible the intellectual progress of the mass and not only of small intellectual groups.[44]
As with the Bolsheviks, the Socialist Party works to weld âintellectualsâ (writers, organizers, etc.) with scant âtraditionalâ education together with those of high âtraditionalâ education in a single comradeship without tiers.
Gramsci also draws a contrast with the old Socialist Party: âa paternalistic party of petty bourgeois with a ridiculous sense of self-importance,â which had âa fatalistic and mechanistic conception of historyâ and yet âa total lack of understanding of [the working classâs] latent energies.â[45] The old Socialist Party membership had been 90+% worker and peasant; but its leaders were mostly people of âtraditionalâ high education, and there was little effort to develop âintellectualsâ from the rank and file. The partyâs culture was oratorical and agitational, rather than written and precise. âThe political parties: they were hardly solid, and they lacked consistent vitality; they only sprung into action during electoral campaigns. The newspapers: their connections with the political parties were weak, and few people read them.â[46]
In contrast, Gramsci outlined the requirements for solid socialist organizing:
This organic continuity requires a good archive, well stocked and easy to use, in which all past activity can be reviewed and âcriticisedâ. The most important manifestations of this activity are not so much âorganic decisionsâ as explicative and reasoned (educative) circulars. There is a danger of becoming âbureaucratisedâ, it is true; but every organic continuity presents this danger, which must be watched. The danger of discontinuity, of improvisation, is still greater. Organ: the âBulletinâ, which has three principal sections: 1. directive articles; 2. decisions and circulars; 3. criticism of the past, i.e. continual reference back from the present to the past, to show the differentiations and the specifications, and to justify them critically.[47]
To start searching for the âusable Gramsciâ in the elements of his Notebooks highlighted by the PCI and Eurocommunist traditions (hegemony in general, war of position, East vs. West) is, I think, to choose the wrong entry-point. Better start where Gramsci himself saw his main focus. |P
[1] Jan Norden, âRevolutionary Trotskyism vs. Gramscism: The Programmatic Clash,â The Internationalist (August 2021), available online at <http://www.internationalist.org/trotskyism-vs-gramscism-2108.html>.
[2] Ibid.
[3] Massimo Amadori, âThe Revolutionary Legacy of Antonio Gramsci,â Socialist Alternative, February 7, 2021, available online at <https://www.socialistalternative.org/2021/02/07/the-revolutionary-legacy-of-antonio-gramsci/>.
[4] Ibid.
[5] V. I. Lenin, âThose Who Would Liquidate Us,â in Lenin Collected Works, vol. 17 (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1963), 60â81, available online at <https://www.marxists.org/archive/lenin/works/1911/twwliqus>.
[6] LâOrdine Nuovo was a newspaper established in May 1919 by a group within the Italian Socialist Party; not to be confused with the organization Ordine Nuovo, which was founded in 1956 by Pino Rauti.
[7] Antonio Gramsci, âOn the LâOrdine Nuovo Programme,â in Selections from Political Writings 1910â20 (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 2003), 293.
[8] Antonio Gramsci, Further Selections from the Prison Notebooks, trans. Derek Boothman (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1995), 385.
[9] Michael Denning, âEveryone a Legislator,â New Left Review 129 (May/June 2021).
[10] Ibid.
[11] Ibid.
[12] Ibid.
[13] Ibid.
[14] Ibid.
[15] Ibid.
[16] Antonio Gramsci, âWho is a Legislator?,â in Selections from the Prison Notebooks (New York: International Publishers, 1971), 265â66.
[17] Ibid., 322.
[18] Denning, âEveryone a Legislator.â
[19] Nicholas Stender, âAntonio Gramsci: A communist revolutionary, organizer, and theorist,â Liberation School (January 1, 2021), available online at <https://liberationschool.org/antonio-gramsci/>.
[20] Antonio Gramsci, âRevolutionaries and the Elections,â in Selections from Political Writings 1910â20, 128.
[21] Stender, âAntonio Gramsci.â
[22] Antonio Gramsci, âThe Formation of the Intellectuals,â in Selections from the Prison Notebooks, 5â7.
[23] Antonio Gramsci, Prison Notebooks, vol. 2, ed. Joseph A. Buttigieg (New York: Columbia University Press, 1975), 242.
[24] AdriĂ Porta CaballĂ©, âErnesto Laclau (1935â2014),â rs21 (April 16, 2014), available online at <https://www.rs21.org.uk/2014/04/16/ernesto-laclau-1935-2014/>.
[25] Chris Maisano, âThe Marxism of Antonio Gramsci and What âHegemonyâ Really Means,â Jacobin Stay at Home Podcast (April 16, 2020), available online at <https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=vBTRI1QDpaY>.
[26] Ibid.
[27] Ibid.
[28] Ibid.
[29] Antonio Gramsci, âSome Theoretical and Practical Aspects of âEconomism,ââ in Selections from the Prison Notebooks, 168.
[30] Francesco Giliani, âHegemony, war of manoeuvre and position: what remains of Gramsci in Gramscism?,â In Defense of Marxism (January 22, 2021), available online at <https://www.marxist.com/gramsci-hegemony-prison-notebooks-1.htm>.
[31] Ibid.
[32] Maisano, âThe Marxism of Antonio Gramsci.â
[33] For efforts at a revolutionary âusable Gramsciâ back then, see, for example, Cliff Slaughter, âWhat is Revolutionary Leadership?,â Labour Review 5, no. 3 (OctoberâNovember 1960), available online at <https://www.marxists.org/history/etol/writers/slaughter/1960/10/leadership.html>; and the references to Gramsci in Contre Althusser, ed. Jean-Marie Vincent (Paris: Union gĂ©nĂ©rale dâĂ©ditions, 1974).
[34] Peter D. Thomas, in chapter 2 of his The Gramscian Moment: Philosophy, Hegemony and Marxism (2011), disputes Andersonâs claim of slippages. I think Anderson was right. See Martin Thomas, âAndersonâs antinomies,â in Gramsci in Context: Essays and Interviews, ed. Martin Thomas (London: Workersâ Liberty, 2014).
[35] Gramsci, Selections from the Prison Notebooks, 120.
[36] Ibid., 231â32.
[37] Ibid., 285â86.
[38] Ibid., 232.
[39] Gramsci, Further Selections from the Prison Notebooks, 395â96.
[40] Antonio Gramsci, Subaltern Social Groups: A Critical Edition of Prison Notebook 25, ed. and trans. Joseph A. Buttigieg and Marcus E. Green (New York: Columbia University Press, 2021), xxxiâxlvii.
[41] Gramsci, Selections from the Prison Notebooks, 196â97.
[42] Ibid., 196â99.
[43] Ibid., 350.
[44] Ibid., 331â33.
[45] Gramsci, Prison Notebooks, vol. 2, 41.
[46] Antonio Gramsci, Prison Notebooks, vol. 3, ed. and trans. Joseph A. Buttigieg (New York: Columbia University Press, 2007), 80.
[47] Gramsci, Selections from the Prison Notebooks, 196.